Published in Foundations of Physics, 26 (1996) 1669-1691 | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Relativistic Quantum Events.
Ph. Blanchard 1and A. Jadczyk 2
1
1Faculty of Physics and BiBoS, University of Bielefeld Universitätstr. 25, D-33615 Bielefeld 2Institute of Theoretical Physics, University of Wroclaw Pl. Maxa Borna 9, PL-50 204 Wroclaw
Abstract: Standard Quantum Theory is inadequate to explain the mechanisms by which potential becomes actual. Is inadequate and therefore unable to describe generation of events. Niels Bohr emphasized long ago that the classical part of the world is necessary. John Bell stressed the same point: that ``measurement" cannot even be defined within the Standard Quantum Theory, and he sought a solution within hidden variable theories and his concept of ``beables." Today it is customary to try to explain emergence of the classical world through a decoherence mechanism due to ``environment". But, we believe, as it was with the concept of measurement, ``environment" itself cannot be defined within the Standard Quantum Theory. We have proposed a semi-phenomenological solution to this problem by introducing explicitly, from the very beginning, classical degrees of freedom, and by coupling these degrees of freedom, through a Lindblad type coupling, to the quantum world. The resulting theory, we call ``Event Enhanced Quantum Theory". EEQT allows us to describe an event generating mechanism for individual quantum systems under continuous observation. The objections of John Bell are met and precise definitions of an ``experiment" and of a ``measurement" have been given within EEQT. However EEQT is, essentially, a non-relativistic theory. In the present paper we extend the ideas of L.P. Horwitz and C. Piron and we propose a relativistic version of EEQT, with an event generating algorithm for spin one-half particle detectors. The algorithm is based on proper time formulation of the relativistic quantum theory. Although we use indefinite metric, all the probabilities controlling the random process of the detector clicks are non-negative.
1. Introduction.Quantum Theory has significantly changed our perspective on what Reality truly is. Prior to Bohr and Heisenberg, speculations about Reality were in the domain of philosophy and not of physics. For a physicist, it was clear that there was a Reality ``out there", and that physics was about making as precise a description of this reality as possible. This Reality had two kinds of concepts connected to it: static concepts and dynamic concepts. Static concepts were ``objects," ``properties" of these objects, and ``relations" between the objects. Dynamic concepts were those of ``events"; defined as ``changes of property," or ``changes of relation." And, ``change" was understood as ``change in time". With the advent of Quantum Theory the existence of this kind of simple reality was first questioned and later denied. Even if quantum physicists still used the concept of an ``object," it was no longer possible to speak about the actual properties and relations of said objects. A fortiori ``events" also disappeared from the vocabulary of quantum theory. Instead of objects and events, another concept emerged as the dominant idea - that of ``measurement" or ``observation". There were however, physicists who were not dominated by the new idea. Some of them, the most prominent ones in this camp being Albert Einstein and David Bohm, believed that quantum theory is a temporary statistical description of some complex nonlinear substructure - yet to be identified. But opposition also appeared in Quantum Theory's own camp. John A. Wheeler stressed repeatedly [1]: ``No elementary quantum phenomenon is a phenomenon until it is a registered (``observed," ``indelibly recorded") phenomenon." But, he did not give a definition of ``being recorded" - and we now understand why? Because such a definition could not be given within the orthodox quantum theory. John Bell [2,3] was the first to clearly realize that the concepts of ``measurement" and ``observation" were being used in Quantum Theory to brainwash physicists into believing that these concepts are a part of Quantum Theory, while in reality they belong to a metastructure. He had the courage to say [4]: ``Either the wave function is not everything or it is not right..." and he opted for an extended theory that would contain, in addition to the quantum wave function, classical variables, which he termed ``beables" - for ``being able to be" [5]. These theories were, however, inconsistent. The classical part was acted upon (by the wave function) but there was no back reaction. There was thus no way to falsify these theories as no new results were predicted that would go beyond those predicted by the textbook recipes of the standard quantum theory. It is our opinion that ``events" are classical in nature. They obey the classical ``yes-no" decision logic. Even if the decisions are based on fuzzy criteria - they are always sharp ``yes-no" decisions. They are points at which choices are being made. Those who adhere to the Many World Interpretation [6] would say: they are points at which the Universe splits into branches. Until we understand the true nature of quantum theory and the true nature of time, these choices must be considered as irreversible. What was done in the past cannot be undone later on. In a series of papers (see [7] and references there) we have developed a semi-phenomenological theory of events - Event Enhanced Quantum Theory (EEQT). The theory is based on the linear time of Galileo and Newton. It is a theory of a special kind of irreversible coupling between quantum and classical systems. 2 Events are defined in this theory as changes of state of the classical subsystem. They are accompanied by quantum jumps - discrete changes of the quantum state. In this theory, the Schrödinger equation is replaced by a piecewise deterministic algorithm that simulates the behavior of an individual quantum system coupled to a classical ``measuring device". We believe that the fundamental laws of Nature, that is the laws that Nature herself uses while producing the events of the world ``out there," are based on algorithms rather than on differential equations. These algorithms are discrete and probabilistic. The latter property mirrors the fact that we have to describe an infinitely complex universe with the finite means that are, at present, at our disposal. A brief description of EEQT will be given in the the following Section. The simplest model that can be taken as an example for building more sophisticated ones is the cloud chamber model developed in [12,13]. It describes an irreversible coupling between a nonrelativistic quantum particle and an arbitrary number of detectors sensitive to the presence of the particle in localized areas of space. From the very moment EEQT was born, we were aware of the unavoidable difficulties that might arise when the nonrelativistic theory would have to be replaced by one that is in agreement with Einstein's Relativity. The difficulties to be addressed in any attempt at building a relativistic theory of quantum measurement have long been known by the experts. (see [14], and for a recent discussion [15]). In a recent paper [16] we anticipated that the solution to this problem would have to involve algorithms that are non-local not only in space but also in time: ``However, if you try to work out a relativistic cloud chamber model (...) the events must be also smeared out in the coordinate time. (...). Nevertheless they can still be sharp in a different ``time", called ``proper time" after Fock and Schwinger." The proper time model of the cloud chamber is presented in Section 3. We have chosen relativistic spin
2. Nonrelativistic Quantum Events.We reiterate, together with John A. Wheeler: No elementary quantum phenomenon is a phenomenon until it is a registered phenomenon. And, physics is about phenomena. The goal of physics is to understand Nature's phenomena; to be able to construct an ``artificial Nature" much in the way the goal of biology is to be able to construct artificial life, the same way the ultimate goal of the computer sciences is to create artificial intelligence. But to construct artificial Nature we must be able to reproduce, in terms of mathematical symbols, the natural phenomena. In order to do this we first must be able to define within mathematics what a phenomenon is. Or, more precisely, what a ``registered phenomenon" is. For this purpose, we will call an elementary registered phenomenon an event. And now we must define what constitutes an event in terms of the mathematical structure. We believe that it is obviously impossible to do this within the standard mathematical framework of the orthodox quantum theory. The framework must be extended, the theory must be enhanced. And, it so happens that the extension is, in fact, only a slight one. Significantly, nothing new is needed that has not already been discussed in the framework of a general algebraic quantum theory. The extension we have in mind consists of allowing algebraic quantities that are not in any kind of uncertainty relation to any other quantity, that is, allowing classical (in algebraic terms they are called ``central") quantities. In other words: a phenomenon can be registered, and an event can happen only if there is a classical subsystem of the given quantum system. It could be said, strictly speaking, that in a pure quantum world nothing could or would ever ``happen." But we see that things do happen in the world out there. This creates an obvious contradiction. One possibility to get us out of the contradiction is to negate events and phenomena, to call them ``illusion," to admit only ``approximate events". This is the road that most quantum physicists of our day are prepared to take. The other possibility is to accept that events do happen and to then introduce explicitly a classical subsystem. In this way, an event is defined as a change of state of this subsystem. This then gives us two further options. One option consists of admitting only mental events. That is to say, events do exist, they do happen, they are not illusions, but they happen only in mind. This is the option advocated by H. P. Stapp [18,19]. We are taking a less adventurous position by leaving the question ``what is truly and intrinsically classical?" open, or ``to be investigated." Therefore our theory, at the present stage, is semi-phenomenological. That is, we are building models that aim at reflecting some of the mechanisms of Nature, but which always can be improved by including more and more details in the description. A general scheme of EEQT has been described in detail in Ref. [7] (see also [17] for a short version). Here we will specify the scheme to the particular but important case of a particle position detector. We must note that in the literature it is common to meet the opinion that any quantum measurement can be, in the last instance, reduced to position measurements. Although we do not share this conclusion, we believe that modelling particle position detectors is important and allows us to understand the mechanism through which other types of quantum phenomena are being registered as events.
2.1 Particle detectorsWe consider a nonrelativistic particle on a line. When no detector is switched on then the quantum mechanical wave function
with a real potential
where
PDP Algorithm 1 Suppose that at time ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]() with the initial wave function
![]() At
![]() The evolution starts now again and it obeys the standard unitary Schrödinger equation with the Hamiltonian
2.2 ``Proper time" formulationIn this subsection we will give a four-dimensional formulation of the nonrelativistic counter click model. It will essentially be just another formulation of the model above. We will see that in a certain limit it approximates the PDP algorithm of the previous subsection. The Hilbert space we consider is now
There is an extra time parameter associated with the counter, we will denote it by
where
The equation (3) for which solves to: It is clear from this that identifying the coordinate time
Remark We have chosen the function
3. Relativistic Quantum Events.Let us now consider the relativistic case. Proper time formulation of the relativistic quantum mechanics has been considered by many authors. We shall cite here the classical paper by Horwitz and Piron [21]. There are also two review papers, one by Kyprianidis [22], and one by Fanchi [23] (cf. also [24]), where more references can be found. While the case of spinless particle was relatively straightforward, the case of spin
and define an indefinite metric space by
where
Let us consider now a particle position detector which, for simplicity, is at rest with respect to the coordinate system. We associate with it the operator
where
Relativistic PDP Algorithm 1 Suppose that at proper time ![]() ![]() ![]() ![]()
with the initial wave function
![]() At
![]() If, after the first click, the detector is deactivated, then after the click the evolution starts again and it obeys the standard unitary Schrödinger equation with the Hamiltonian The algorithm contains second order, proper time, Dirac equation. This equation can be geometrically derived by the method of dimensional reduction along an isotropic Killing vector field in six dimensional space of signature
where the functions
The algorithm proceeds as before but now, when the event happens at
Generalization to a larger number of detectors, that are not necessarily at rest, is straightforward. 4. Final Remarks.We have proposed a relativistic PDP algorithm that allows one to model the behavior of a detector coupled to a relativistic spin In the nonrelativistic case there is a dual description: by a continuous in time Liouville equation that describes time evolution of statistical states, and by the PDP Algorithm that simulates Nature's event generation for individual systems. In the relativistic case we have restricted ourselves to the individual description. In fact, at present, we do not know what would be the right mathematical formalism and its physical interpretation for a relativistic analogue of the Liouville equation. Formally we can write an equation as in the nonrelativistic case, but now using an indefinite metric space. Some of the relevant mathematics have been developed in the past by one of us [33]. What is yet to be done is to study the nonrelativistic limit of the Relativistic PDP and to see that Nonrelativistic PDP of EEQT is recovered this way. The ideas given in the papers by Horwitz [34] and Horwitz and Rotbart [35] can be applied for studying such a limit. Other problems that are yet to be investigated are: quantum field theoretical generalization along the lines of Ref. [13], and an explicit formula for time-of-click probability for a pointlike detector and a special intitial wave packet - as in Ref. [16]. It is to be observed that a quantum field theoretical version will have to involve, as it was for one particle, indefinite metric. It must be noted that the Relativistic PDP, in cases of more than one detector, involves non-local decision making algorithm. Thus, even if the detectors are treated as classical in our approach, nevertheless there is no local explanation for their behavior. To decide which of the two detectors will click at the event time involves a random choice based on probabilities that are computed non-locally. How Nature herself is doing this - is a big puzzle. A solution to this puzzle must be postponed till a later time when the very nature and origin of the Planck constant, of space and of time are better understood.
Acknowledgment(s)One of us (A.J.) would like to thank the A. von Humboldt Foundation for support. He would also like to thank Larry Horwitz for encouragement and discussion, and Laura Knight for reading the manuscript.
Bibliography
Footnotes
|
|